Tuesday , March 19 2024
Home / Real-World Economics Review / Ontology, framing, and all that jazz

Ontology, framing, and all that jazz

Summary:
From Peter Radford The collection of papers edited by Uskali Mäki and published in 2001 under the title: “The Economic World View, Studies in the Ontology of Economics” seems to be quite pertinent given the reaction to my recent comments on complexity.  It is a wonderfully rich source of thought about what, exactly, economics is, which is something that seems to confound a great number of people.  Quite often I get the sense that some critics are upset with economics because it isn’t physics, or chemistry, or, more controversially, biology.  No it isn’t.  Nor are they economics.  Hopefully we all agree on that.  Nor is it history or any other thing.  It is economics.  Which is something that has coalesced around certain ideas over the last couple of hundred years.  Quite what it is,

Topics:
Peter Radford considers the following as important:

This could be interesting, too:

Peter Radford writes Weekend read – The trouble with words

Dean Baker writes In a free market, drugs are cheap, government-granted patent monopolies make them expensive

Lars Pålsson Syll writes I heard there’s some good shit on TV tonight …

Dean Baker writes Is “greedflation” over?

from Peter Radford

The collection of papers edited by Uskali Mäki and published in 2001 under the title: “The Economic World View, Studies in the Ontology of Economics” seems to be quite pertinent given the reaction to my recent comments on complexity.  It is a wonderfully rich source of thought about what, exactly, economics is, which is something that seems to confound a great number of people.  Quite often I get the sense that some critics are upset with economics because it isn’t physics, or chemistry, or, more controversially, biology.  No it isn’t.  Nor are they economics.  Hopefully we all agree on that.  Nor is it history or any other thing.  It is economics.  Which is something that has coalesced around certain ideas over the last couple of hundred years.  Quite what it is, though, remains a work in progress.

Economics is way more complex than the “natural” sciences simply because it involves us and our confounded intentionality, controversy, whimsy, and so on.  Physicist have it easy: atoms don’t “think”.  Which is why those economists who try to nail people down as if they are atoms do what they do.  It simplifies what is otherwise an enormous fog.  I happen to think they oversimplify, but I don’t criticize them for trying.

Buried in Mäki’s own contribution, which is rather cheekily entitled “The way the world works”, is an illuminating comment from Ronald Coase who, as you know, is one of my favorite economists.  Coase let’s us know that he sees the relentless fixation on economics as being a theory of choice as harmful because it detracts from other significant features of real economies:

“This preoccupation of economists with the logic of choice … has nonetheless had, in my view, serious adverse effects on economics itself.  One result of this divorce of the theory from its subject matter has been that the entities whose decisions economists are engaged in analyzing have not been made the subject of study and in consequence lack any substance.  The consumer is not a human being but a consistent set of preferences.  The firm to an economist … ‘is effectively defined as a cost curve and a demand curve’ .  Exchange takes place without any specification of its institutional setting.  We have consumers without humanity, firms without organization, and even exchange without markets.”  — Coase, 1988, “The Firm, the Market, and the Law”.

Narrowing economics down to being a theory of choice fits within the tradition of what I have called, at my peril apparently, the war on scarcity.  It allows for the excessive formalization I and many others decry.  It makes economics into a kind of applied mathematics which satisfies the sort of economist who might have started out early in in life studying mathematics, physics and so on, but leaves aside other perspectives that reveal insights intractable to that approach.

The existence of scarcity is a primordial condition of humanity.  The battle for subsistence in a landscape that presented few opportunities for prosperity was the basis of existence for millennia.  It created the illusion of stability.  Yet within each of those periods there was a low level but relentless improvement taking place.  Invention or innovation was slowly allowing our ancestors to cope better with scarcity.  In other words despite the illusion of stasis it was becoming possible to tame nature.  We were winning the battle with scarcity.

Eventually, of course, it was possible for the economy, whatever we decide that is, to escape from the social and ethical limits put on it through those millennia.  There is even a good argument to be made that it was entirely due to the steady erosion of scarcity that society became affluent enough to turn its attention to costly activities such as religion, politics, and state building.  What appeals to me about economics is that it is the study of how that affluence is created and distributed.  Or, rather, that’s my basic point of view.  And in order to get at answers to those questions we need to think about what an economy is. Which is where I wander into thinking about information and so on.

Which returns me to the Mäki article.  Information is something economists talk about a great deal.  It is usually in the context of communication rather than structure or learning in the way that Hidalgo sees information.  To my mind this is excessively narrow, but it is the way in which economists devoted their early attention to information.  Mäki quotes Richardson, another of my favorite thinkers on economics, as being critical of how restrictive this focus on communication has become:

“if we are led to study the informational aspects of social systems only in terms of a rigid conceptual framework borrowed from physics, we shall certainly obtain a distorted picture.  Prices, for example, and particularly the current values of prices, assume from this point of view an undeserved prominence, because it is in terms of them that a quasi-physical signaling mechanism can be elaborated and given mathematical expression.”  Richardson, 1960, “Information and Investment”

Richardson’s belief is that looking at an economy is such a limited and almost mechanical way leaves too much out.  I agree.  Which is why I think we need to look for an expression of reality that better accommodates itself to the task of economics.

But that brings us back to deciding what task[s] that is.

To reveal my hand a little more, two articles in the Mäki book stand out to me: “Economics without mechanism” by John Dupre; and Jack Vromen’s”Ontological commitments of evolutionary economics”.  The latter, in particular, is worthy of further discussion as we all ponder what economics is.

Before I came across the Mäki collection I was influenced by Tony Lawson’s “Economics and Reality”.  So I will end this little grab bag of thought with a longish quote from Lawson as he gets to grips with the issues of economics:

“Economics, then, in a more obvious way than natural science perhaps, is necessarily historical-geographical.  In addition, if by virtue of their dependency upon human agency, social structures must continually be reproduced, it follows that economics is concerned with inherently dynamic matters.  The terminology of process is thus fundamental to social science.  By this I do not mean … merely a sequence of events.  Rather, process denotes here the genesis, reproduction, and decline of some structure mechanism or thing, the formation, reformation and decay of some entity in time.  Clearly, if society is intrinsically dynamic, social science must be alert, and its methods tailored to, this condition.  Furthermore, the dependence of social structure upon human agency also entails an inescapable hermeneutic moment in social science, one that … may be of greater consequences than any similar or comparable moment in natural science.  In addition, the impossibility of engineering, and the absence of spontaneously occurring, closed social systems, necessitates a reliance upon non-predictive, purely explanatory, criteria of theory development and assessment in the social sciences.

One last thing, the introduction in Robert Ayres terrific book “Information, Entropy, and Progress: A New Evolutionary Paradigm” sets up the terms and concepts nicely for anyone who wants to follow Lawson’s path.  It’s always worth remembering that the paths we tread are well-worn, and that, more often or not, our revelations are humdrum in the context of the entire conversation that is economics.  The classic along this path, of course, is Georgescu-Roegen’s “The Entropy Law and the Economic Process”.  But that’s for another day.

Peter Radford
Peter Radford is publisher of The Radford Free Press, worked as an analyst for banks over fifteen years and has degrees from the London School of Economics and Harvard Business School.

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *