Tuesday , November 5 2024
Home / Lars P. Syll / ‘Covering law’ explanations in economics

‘Covering law’ explanations in economics

Summary:
‘Covering law’ explanations in economics As a philosopher of science, it is interesting to note that many economists and other social scientists appeal to a requirement that explanations, in order to be considered scientific, must be capable of “reducing an individual case to a general law.” As a fundamental principle, a general law is often invoked in the form of “if A, then B,” and if one can demonstrate in individual cases that if A and B are present, then one has ‘explained’ B. However, this positivist-inductive view of science is fundamentally untenable. Let me explain why. According to a positivist-inductive view of science, the knowledge possessed by science constitutes proven knowledge. By starting with entirely unbiased observations, an

Topics:
Lars Pålsson Syll considers the following as important:

This could be interesting, too:

Lars Pålsson Syll writes Daniel Waldenströms rappakalja om ojämlikheten

Peter Radford writes AJR, Nobel, and prompt engineering

Lars Pålsson Syll writes MMT explained

Lars Pålsson Syll writes Statens finanser funkar inte som du tror

‘Covering law’ explanations in economics

As a philosopher of science, it is interesting to note that many economists and other social scientists appeal to a requirement that explanations, in order to be considered scientific, must be capable of “reducing an individual case to a general law.” As a fundamental principle, a general law is often invoked in the form of “if A, then B,” and if one can demonstrate in individual cases that if A and B are present, then one has ‘explained’ B.

However, this positivist-inductive view of science is fundamentally untenable. Let me explain why.

‘Covering law’ explanations in economicsAccording to a positivist-inductive view of science, the knowledge possessed by science constitutes proven knowledge. By starting with entirely unbiased observations, an ‘impartial scientific observer’ can formulate observational statements from which scientific theories and laws can be derived. Using the principle of induction, it becomes possible to formulate universal statements in the form of laws and theories that refer to occurrences of properties that hold always and everywhere. Based on these laws and theories, science can derive various consequences with which one can explain and predict what happens. Through logical deduction, statements can be derived from other statements. The logic of research follows the schema of observation — induction — deduction.

In more uncomplicated cases, scientists must conduct experiments to justify the inductions with which they establish their scientific theories and laws. As Francis Bacon so vividly put it, experimentation involves “putting nature on the rack” and forcing it to answer our questions. With the help of a set of statements that accurately describe the circumstances surrounding the experiment – initial conditions – and the scientific laws, scientists can deduce statements that can explain or predict the phenomenon under investigation.

The hypothetico-deductive method for scientific explanations and predictions can be described in general terms as follows:

1 Laws and theories

2 Initial conditions

——————

3 Explanations and predictions

.

According to one of the main proponents of the hypothetico-deductive method, Carl Hempel, all scientific explanations have this form, which can also be expressed using the following schema:

All A are B Premise 1

a is A Premise 2

——————————

a is B Conclusion

.

As an example, let’s consider the following everyday phenomenon:

Water boils when heated to 100 degrees Celsius

This pot of water is heated to 100 degrees Celsius

———————————————————————–

This pot of water boils

.

The problem with the hypothetico-deductive method lies not so much in premise 2 or the conclusion but in the hypothesis itself, premise 1. This is the part that must be proven to be true, and this is where the process of induction comes in.

The most obvious weakness of the hypothetico-deductive method is the principle of induction. The most common justification for it goes as follows:

The principle of induction worked on occasion 1

The principle of induction worked on occasion 2

The principle of induction worked on occasion n

—————————————————–

The principle of induction always works

.

However, this is questionable because the ‘proof’ uses induction to justify induction. One cannot use singular statements about the validity of the principle of induction to derive a universal statement about the validity of the principle of induction.

Induction is intended to play two roles. Firstly, it is supposed to enable generalization, and secondly, it is assumed to provide evidence for the truth of conclusions. However, as the problem of induction shows, induction cannot fulfil both of these tasks. It can increase the probability of conclusions (assuming that the principle of induction is correct, which cannot be proven without circular reasoning), but it does not guarantee that these conclusions are necessarily true.

Another often-mentioned weakness of the hypothetico-deductive method is that theories always precede observational statements and experiments, so it is incorrect to claim that science starts with observations and experiments. Additionally, observational statements and experiments cannot be assumed to be straightforwardly reliable, and their validation requires reference to theory. The reliability of theories themselves is not primarily resolved by more observations and experiments but by the development of alternative and better theories. One can also argue that induction does not enable us to acquire knowledge about the underlying structures and mechanisms of reality but only about empirical generalizations and regularities. In science, the explanation of events at one level is often found in causes at another, deeper level. The inductivist view of science describes the main task of science as indicating how something happens, while other theories of science argue that the primary task of science must be to explain why it happens.

As a result of the aforementioned problems, more moderate empiricists have reasoned that since there is usually no logical procedure for discovering a law or theory, one simply starts with laws and theories from which a series of statements that serve as explanations or predictions are deduced. Instead of investigating how scientific laws and theories are arrived at, the focus is on explaining what a scientific explanation and prediction are, the role theories and models play in them, and how they can be evaluated.

In the positivist (hypothetico-deductive, deductive-nomological) model of explanation, explanation refers to the subordination or derivation of specific phenomena from universal regularities. To explain a phenomenon (explanandum) is the same as deducing a description of it from a set of premises and universal laws of the form “If A, then B” (explanans). Explanation simply involves being able to place something under a specific regularity, and this approach is sometimes referred to as the “covering law model”. However, theories should not be used to explain specific individual phenomena but to explain the universal regularities that are part of a hypothetico-deductive explanation. [But there are problems with this view even in natural science. Many of the laws of natural science do not really say what things do but rather what they tend to do. This is largely due to the fact that the laws describe the behaviour of different parts rather than the entire phenomenon itself (except possibly in experimental situations). And many of the laws of natural science actually apply to fictional entities rather than real ones. Often, this is a consequence of the use of mathematics within the respective science and leads to the fact that its laws can only be exemplified in models (and not in reality).] The positivist model of explanation also exists in a weaker variant known as the probabilistic explanation, according to which explaining essentially means showing that the probability of an event B is very high if event A occurs. This variant dominates in the social sciences. From a methodological standpoint, this probabilistic relativization of the positivist explanatory approach does not make a significant difference.

One consequence of accepting the hypothetico-deductive model of explanation is often the acceptance of the so-called symmetry thesis. According to this thesis, the only difference between prediction and explanation is that in the former, the explanans is assumed to be known, and a prediction is attempted, while in the latter, the explanandum is assumed to be known, and the goal is to find initial conditions and laws from which the observed phenomenon can be derived.

However, a problem with the symmetry thesis is that it does not consider that causes can be confused with correlations. The fact that storks appear at the same time as human babies does not explain the origin of children.

The symmetry thesis also fails to acknowledge that causes can be sufficient but not necessary. The fact that a cancer patient gets run over does not make cancer the cause of death. Cancer could have been the actual explanation for the individual’s death. Even if we could construct a medical law – in accordance with the deductive model – stating that individuals with a specific type of cancer will die from that cancer, the law does not explain this individual’s death. Therefore, the thesis is simply incorrect.

Finding a pattern is not the same as explaining something. To receive the answer that the bus is usually late when asking why it is delayed does not constitute an acceptable explanation. Ontology and natural necessity must be part of a relevant answer, at least if one seeks something more than “constant conjunctions of events” in an explanation.

The original idea behind the positivist model of explanation was to provide a complete clarification of what an explanation is and to show that an explanation that did not meet its requirements was actually a pseudo-explanation. It aimed to provide a method for testing explanations and demonstrate that explanations in accordance with the model were the goal of science. Clearly, all these claims can be legitimately questioned.

An important reason why this model has gained traction in science is that it seemed to offer a way to explain things without needing to use ‘metaphysical’ notions of causality. Many scientists see causality as a problematic concept that should be avoided if possible. Simple observable variables should suffice. The problem is that specifying these variables and their possible correlations does not explain anything at all. The fact that union representatives often wear gray suits and employer representatives wear pinstriped suits does not explain why youth unemployment in Sweden is so high today. What is missing in these “explanations” is the necessary adequacy, relevance, and causal depth without which science risks becoming empty science fiction and a mere playground for models.

Many social scientists seem to be convinced that in order for research to be considered science, it must apply some variant of the hypothetico-deductive method. From the complex array of facts and events in reality, one should extract a few common lawful correlations that can serve as explanations. Within certain fields of social science, this endeavour to reduce explanations of social phenomena to a few general principles or laws has been a significant driving force. By employing a few general assumptions, the aim is to explain the nature of an entire macrophenomenon we call society. Unfortunately, there are no truly sustainable arguments provided as to why the fact that a theory can explain different phenomena in a unified manner would be a decisive reason to accept or prefer it. Uniformity and adequacy are not synonymous.

Lars Pålsson Syll
Professor at Malmö University. Primary research interest - the philosophy, history and methodology of economics.

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *